Biologie

Irreducible Complexity: Obstacle to Darwinian Evolution

Prof. Dr. Michael J. Behe · 
01.01.2007

Darwinsche Evolution setzt voraus, dass der Zufall die verschiedenen Arten hervorgebracht hat. Allerdings scheint es in der Natur spezifisch komplexe Gebilde zu geben, die irrreduzibel sind, d.h. sie verlieren ihre Funktionalität, wenn auch nur eine Komponente dieses Mechanismus fehlt. Solche Gebilde sind, wie man heute wie, wesentlich komplexer aufgebaut als Darwin dachte. Die Mathematik lehrt uns zudem, dass solche Gebilde sich aber nicht zufällig entwickelt haben können, dazu ist das Universum nicht groß und alt genug. Solche irrreduzible Komplexität in der Biologie ist Gegenstand der nachfolgenden Betrachtungen.

A Sketch of the Intelligent Design Hypothesis

In his seminal work, The Origin of Species, Darwin hoped to explain what no one had been able to explain before—how the variety and complexity of the living world might have been produced by simple natural laws. His idea for doing so was, of course, the theory of evolution by natural selection. In a nutshell, Darwin saw that there was variety in all species. For example, some members of a species are bigger than others, some faster, some brighter in color. He knew that not all organisms that were born would survive to reproduce, simply because there was not enough food to sustain them all. So Darwin reasoned that the ones whose chance variation gave them an edge in the struggle for life would tend to survive and leave offspring. If the variation could be inherited, then over time the characteristics of the species would change, and over great periods of time, perhaps great changes could occur.
It was an elegant idea, and many scientists of the time quickly saw that it could explain many things about biology. However, there remained an important reason for reserving judgment about whether it could actually account for all of biology: the basis of life was yet unknown. In Darwin’s day atoms and molecules were still theoretical constructs—no one was sure if such things actually existed. Many scientists of Darwin’s era took the cell to be a simple glob of protoplasm, something like a microscopic piece of Jell-O. Thus the intricate molecular basis of life was utterly unknown to Darwin and his contemporaries.
In the past hundred years science has learned much more about the cell and, especially in the past fifty years, much about the molecular basis of life. The discoveries of the double helical structure of DNA, the genetic code, the complicated, irregular structure of proteins, and much else have given us a greater appreciation for the elaborate structures that are necessary to sustain life. Indeed, we have seen that the cell is run by machines—literally, machines made of molecules. There are molecular machines that enable the cell to move, machines that empower it to transport nutrients, machines that allow it to defend itself.

In light of the enormous progress made by science since Darwin first proposed his theory, it is reasonable to ask if the theory still seems to be a good explanation for life. In Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution (Behe 1996) I argued that it is not. The main difficulty for Darwinian mechanisms is that many systems in the cell are what I termed “irreducibly complex.” I defined an irreducibly complex system as: a single system which is necessarily composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, and where the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning. (Behe 2001) As an example of an irreducibly complex system from everyday life, I pointed to a mechanical mousetrap such as one finds in a hardware store. Typically such traps have a number of parts: a spring, wooden platform, hammer, and other pieces. If one removes a piece from the trap, it can’t catch mice. Without the spring, or hammer, or the other pieces, one doesn’t have a trap that works half as well as it used to, or a quarter as well; one has a broken mousetrap, which doesn’t work at all.
Irreducibly complex systems seem very difficult to fit into a Darwinian framework, for a reason insisted upon by Darwin himself. In the Origin Darwin wrote that “If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications, my theory would absolutely break down. But I can find out no such case.” (Darwin 1859, 158) Here Darwin was emphasizing that his was a gradual theory. Natural selection had to improve systems by tiny steps, over a long period of time, because if things improved too rapidly, or in large steps, then it would begin to look as if something other than natural selection were driving the process. However, it is hard to see how something like a mousetrap could arise gradually by something akin to a Darwinian process. For example, a spring by itself, or a platform by itself, would not catch mice, and adding a piece to the first nonfunctioning piece wouldn’t make a trap either. So it appears that irreducibly complex biological systems would present a considerable obstacle to Darwinian evolution.
The question then becomes, are there any irreducibly complex systems in the cell? Are there any irreducibly complex molecular machines? Yes, there are many. In Darwin’s Black Box I discussed several biochemical systems as examples of irreducible complexity: the eukaryotic cilium; the intracellular transport system; and more. Here I will just briefly describe the bacterial flagellum (DeRosier 1998;Shapiro 1995), since its structure makes the difficulty for Darwinian evolution easy to see. (Figure 1)

Figure 1. The bacterial flagellum. Reproduced from Voet, D. and Voet, J.G. (1995) Biochemistry, 2 edition, John Wiley & Sons, New York, Figure 34-84, with permission of John Wiley Publishers and Donald Voet, who wished to emphasize that “this is an artist-drawn representation of the flagellum rather than a photo or drawing of an actual flagellum.”

The flagellum can be thought of as an outboard motor that bacteria use to swim. It was the first truly rotary structure discovered in nature. It consists of a long filamentous tail that acts as a propeller; when it is spun it pushes against the liquid medium and can propel the bacterium forward. The propeller is attached to the drive shaft indirectly through something called the hook region, which acts as a universal joint. The drive shaft is attached to the motor, which uses a flow of acid or sodium ions from the outside of the cell to the inside to power rotation. Just as an outboard motor has to be kept stationary on a motorboat while the propeller turns, there are proteins which act as a stator structure to keep the flagellum in place. Other proteins act as bushings to permit the drive shaft to pass through the bacterial membrane. Studies have shown that 30-40 proteins are required to produce a functioning flagellum in the cell. About half of the proteins are components of the finished structure, while the others are necessary for the construction of the flagellum. In the absence of almost any of the proteins—in the absence of the parts that act as the propeller, drive shaft, hook, and so forth—no functioning flagellum is built. As with the mousetrap, it is quite difficult to see how Darwin’s gradualistic process of natural selection sieving random mutations could produce the bacterial flagellum, since many pieces are required before its function appears. A hook by itself, or drive shaft by itself, will not act as a propulsive device. But the situation is actually much worse than it appears from this cursory description, for several reasons. First, there is associated with the functioning of the flagellum an intricate control system, which tells the flagellum when to rotate, when to stop, and sometimes, when to reverse itself and rotate in the opposite direction. This allows the bacterium to swim toward or away from an appropriate signal, rather than in a random direction which could much more easily take it the wrong way. Thus the problem of accounting for the origin of the flagellum is not limited to the flagellum itself, but to associated control systems as well. Second, a more subtle problem is how the parts assemble themselves into a whole. The analogy to an outboard motor fails in one respect: an outboard motor is generally assembled under the direction of a human—an intelligent agent that can specify which parts are attached to which other parts. The information for assembling a bacterial flagellum, however, (or, indeed, all other biomolecular machines) resides in the component proteins of the structure itself. Recent work shows that the assembly process for a flagellum is exceedingly elegant and intricate. (Yonekura et al. 2000) If that assembly information is absent from the proteins, then no flagellum is produced. Thus, even if we had a hypothetical cell in which proteins homologous to all of the parts of the flagellum were present (perhaps performing jobs other than propulsion), but were missing the information on how to assemble themselves into a flagellum, we would still not get the structure. The problem of irreducibility would remain. Because of such considerations, I have concluded that Darwinian processes are not promising explanations for many biochemical systems in the cell. Instead I have noted that, if one looks at the interactions of the components of the flagellum, or cilium, or other irreducibly complex cellular systems, they look like they were designed—purposely designed by an intelligent agent. The features of the systems which indicate design are the same ones which stymie Darwinian explanations: the specific interaction of multiple components to accomplish a function which is beyond the individual components. The logical structure of the argument to design is a simple inductive one: whenever we see such highly specific interactions in our everyday world, whether in a mousetrap or elsewhere, we unfailingly find that the systems were intentionally arranged—that they were designed. Now we find systems of similar complexity in the cell. Since no other explanation has successfully addressed them, I argue we should extend the induction to subsume molecular machines, and hypothesize that they were purposely designed.

Misconceptions About What a Hypothesis of Design Entails

The hypothesis of intelligent design (ID) is quite controversial, mostly because of its philosophical and theological overtones, and in the years since Darwin’s Black Box was published a number of scientists and philosophers have tried to refute its main argument. I have found these rebuttals unpersuasive at best. Quite the opposite, I think that some putative counterexamples to design are unintentionally instructive in that, not only do they fail to make their case for the sufficiency of natural selection, but they show clearly the obstacle that irreducible complexity poses to Darwinism. They also show that Darwinists have great trouble recognizing problems for their own theory. I will examine two of those counterexamples in detail a little later in this chapter. Before I do, however, I will first address a few common misconceptions that surround the biochemical design argument. First of all, it is important to understand that a hypothesis of intelligent design has no quarrel with evolution per se—that is, “evolution” understood simply as descent with modification, but leaving the mechanism open. After all, a designer may have chosen to work that way. Rather than common descent, the focus of ID is on the mechanism of evolution—how did all this happen, by natural selection or by purposeful intelligent design? A second point that is often overlooked but should be emphasized is that intelligent design can happily coexist with even a large degree of natural selection. Antibiotic and pesticide resistance, antifreeze proteins in fish and plants, and more may indeed be explained by a Darwinian mechanism. The critical claim of ID is not that natural selection doesn’t explain anything, but that it doesn’t explain everything. My book, Darwin’s Black Box, in which I flesh out the design argument, has been widely discussed in many publications. Although many issues have been raised, I think the general reaction by scientists to the design argument is well and succinctly summarized in a recent book The Way of the Cell, published by Oxford University Press, and authored by Colorado State University biochemist Franklin Harold. Citing my book, Harold writes, “We should reject, as a matter of principle, the substitution of intelligent design for the dialogue of chance and necessity (Behe 1996); but we must concede that there are presently no detailed Darwinian accounts of the evolution of any biochemical system, only a variety of wishful speculations.” (Harold 2001, 205) Let me emphasize in reverse order Harold’s two points. First, as other reviewers of my book have done [1], he acknowledges that Darwinists have no real explanations for the enormous complexity of the cell, only hand-waving speculations, more colloquially known as “Just-So stories.” I had claimed essentially the same thing six years earlier in Darwin’s Black Box, and encountered fierce resistance—mostly from internet fans of Darwinism who claimed that, why, there were hundreds or thousands of research papers describing the Darwinian evolution of irreducibly complex biochemical systems, and who set up web sites to document them. [2] As a sufficient response to such claims, I will simply rely on Harold’s statement quoted here, as well as the other reviewers who agree that there is a dearth of Darwinian explanations. After all, if prominent scientists who are no fans of intelligent design agree that the systems remain unexplained, then that should settle the matter. Let me pause, however, to note that I find this an astonishing admission for a theory that has dominated biology for so long. That Darwinian theory has borne such little fruit in explaining the molecular basis of life— despite its long reign as the fundamental theory of biology— strongly suggests that it is not the right framework to understand the origin of the complexity of life. Harold’s second point is that he apparently thinks there is some principle that forbids us from investigating intelligent design, even though design is an obvious idea that quickly pops into your mind when you see a drawing of the flagellum (Figure 1) or other complex biochemical systems. What principle is that? He never spells it out, but I think the principle likely boils down to this: Design appears to point strongly beyond nature. It has philosophical and theological implications, and that makes many people uncomfortable. They think that science should avoid a theory that points so strongly beyond nature, and so they want to rule out intelligent design from the start. I completely disagree with that view and find it fainthearted. I think science should follow the evidence wherever it seems to lead. That is the only way to make progress. Furthermore, it is not only intelligent design, but any theory that purports to explain how life occurred will have philosophical and theological implications. For example, the Oxford biologist Richard Dawkins has famously said that “Darwin made it possible to be an intellectually-fulfilled atheist.” (Dawkins 1986, 6) A little less famously, Kenneth Miller has written that “[God] used evolution as the tool to set us free.” (Miller 1999, 253) Stuart Kauffman, a leading complexity theorist, thinks Darwinism cannot explain all of biology: “Darwinism is not enough…
[N]atural selection cannot be the sole source of order we see in the world.” (Kauffman 1995, viii) But he thinks that his theory will somehow show that we are “at home in the universe.” The point, then, is that all theories of origins carry philosophical and theological implications. There is no way to avoid them in an explanation of life. Another source of difficulty for some people concerns the question, how could biochemical systems have been designed? A common misconception is that designed systems would have to be created from scratch in a puff of smoke. But that isn’t necessarily so. The design process may have been much more subtle. In fact, it may have contravened no natural laws at all. Let’s consider just one possibility. Suppose the designer is indeed God, as most people would suspect. Well, then, as Kenneth Miller points out in his book, Finding Darwin’s God: The indeterminate nature of quantum events would allow a clever and subtle God to influence events in ways that are profound, but scientifically undetectable to us. Those events could include the appearance of mutations . . . and even the survival of individual cells and organisms affected by the chance processes of radioactive decay. (Miller 1999, 241) Although Miller doesn’t think guidance is necessary in evolution, if it were, as I believe, then a route would be open for a subtle God to design life without overriding natural law. If quantum events such as radioactive decay are not governed by causal laws, then it breaks no law of nature to influence such events. As a theist like Miller, that seems perfectly possible to me. I would add, however, that such a process would amount to intelligent design, not Darwinian evolution. Further, while we might not be able to detect quantum manipulations, we may be able to conclude confidently that the final structure was designed.

Misconceptions Concerning Supposed Ways Around The Irreducibility of Biochemical Systems

Consider a hypothetical example where proteins homologous to all of the parts of an irreducibly complex molecular machine first had other individual functions in the cell. Might the irreducible system then have been put together from individual components that originally worked on their own, as some Darwinists have proposed? Unfortunately this picture greatly oversimplifies the difficulty, as I discussed in Darwin’s Black Box. (Behe 1996, 53) Here analogies to mousetraps break down somewhat, because the parts of a molecular system have to automatically find each other in the cell. They can’t be arranged by an intelligent agent, as a mousetrap is. To find each other in the cell, interacting parts have to have their surfaces shaped so that they are very closely matched to each other, such as pictured in Figure 2. Originally, however, the individually-acting components would not have had complementary surfaces. So all of the interacting surfaces of all of the components would first have to be adjusted before they could function together. And only then would the new function of the composite system appear. Thus, I emphasize strongly, the problem of irreducibility remains, even if individual proteins homologous to system components separately and originally had their own functions.

Figure 2. The parts of an irreducibly complex molecular machine must have surfaces that are closely matched to each other to allow specific binding. This drawing emphasizes that even if individually-acting proteins homologous to parts of a complex originally had separate functions, their surfaces would not be complementary to each other. Thus the problem of irreducibility remains even if the separate parts originally had individual functions. (The blocked arrows indicate the original protein shapes are not suitable to bind other proteins in the molecular machine.)

Another area where one has to be careful is in noticing that some systems with extra or redundant components may have an irreducibly complex core. For example, a car with four spark plugs might get by with three or two, but it certainly can’t get by with none. Rat traps often have two springs, to give them extra strength. The trap can still work if one spring is removed, but it can’t work if both springs are removed. Thus in trying to imagine the origin of a rat trap by Darwinian means, we still have all the problems we had with a mousetrap. A cellular example of redundancy is the hugely complex eukaryotic cilium, which contains about 250 distinct protein parts. (Dutcher 1995) The cilium has multiple copies of a number of components, including multiple microtubules and dynein arms. Yet a working cilium needs at least one copy of each to work, as I pictured in my book. (Behe 1996, 60) Thus, like a rat trap, its gradual Darwinian production remains quite difficult to envision. Kenneth Miller has pointed to the redundancy of the cilium as a counterexample to my claim of its irreducibility. (Miller 1999, 140-143) But redundancy only delays irreducibility; it does not eliminate it. Finally, rather than showing how their theory could handle the obstacle, some Darwinists are hoping to get around irreducible complexity by verbal tap dancing. At a debate between proponents and opponents of intelligent design sponsored by the American Museum of Natural History in April 2002, Kenneth Miller actually claimed (the transcript is available at the website of the National Center for Science Education) that a mousetrap isn’t irreducibly complex because subsets of a mousetrap, and even each individual part, could still “function” on their own. The holding bar of a mousetrap, Miller observed, could be used as a toothpick, so it still had a “function” outside the mousetrap. Any of the parts of the trap could be used as a paperweight, he continued, so they all had “functions.” And since any object that has mass can be a paperweight, then any part of anything has a function of its own. Presto, there is no such thing as irreducible complexity! Thus the acute problem for gradualism that any child can see in systems like the mousetrap is smoothly explained away. Of course the facile explanation rests on a transparent fallacy, a brazen equivocation. Miller uses the word “function” in two different senses. Recall that the definition of irreducible complexity notes that removal of a part “causes the system to effectively cease functioning.” Without saying so, in his exposition Miller shifts the focus from the separate function of the intact system itself to the question of whether we can find a different use (or “function”) for some of the parts. However, if one removes a part from the mousetrap I pictured, it can no longer catch mice. The system has indeed effectively ceased functioning, so the system is irreducibly complex, just as I had written. What’s more, the functions that Miller glibly assigns to the parts—paperweight, toothpick, key chain, etc.—have little or nothing to do with the function of the system of catching mice (unlike the mousetrap series proposed by John McDonald, discussed below), so they give us no clue as to how the system’s function could arise gradually. Miller explained precisely nothing. With the problem of the mousetrap behind him, Miller moved on to the bacterial flagellum—and again resorted to the same fallacy. If nothing else, one has to admire the breathtaking audacity of verbally trying to turn another severe problem for Darwinism into an advantage. In recent years it has been shown that the bacterial flagellum is an even more sophisticated system than had been thought. Not only does it act as a rotary propulsion device, it also contains within itself an elegant mechanism to transport the proteins that make up the outer portion of the machine, from the inside of the cell to the outside. (Aizawa 1996) Without blinking, Miller asserted that the flagellum is not irreducibly complex because some proteins of the flagellum could be missing and the remainder could still transport proteins, perhaps independently. (Proteins similar— but not identical—to some found in the flagellum occur in the type III secretory system of some bacteria. See Hueck 1998). Again he was equivocating, switching the focus from the function of the system to act as a rotary propulsion machine to the ability of a subset of the system to transport proteins across a membrane. However, taking away the parts of the flagellum certainly destroys the ability of the system to act as a rotary propulsion machine, as I have argued. Thus, contra Miller, the flagellum is indeed irreducibly complex. What’s more, the function of transporting proteins has as little directly to do with the function of rotary propulsion as a toothpick has to do with a mousetrap. So discovering the supportive function of transporting proteins tells us precisely nothing about how Darwinian processes might have put together a rotary propulsion machine.

The Blood Clotting Cascade

Having dealt with some common misconceptions about intelligent design, in the next several sections I will examine two systems that were proposed as serious counterexamples to my claim of irreducible complexity. I will show not only that they fail, but also how they highlight the seriousness of the obstacle of irreducible complexity. In Darwin’s Black Box I argued that the blood clotting cascade is an example of an irreducibly complex system. (Behe 1996, 74-97) As seen just by eye, clotting seems like a simple process. A small cut or scrape will bleed for a while and then slow down and stop as the visible blood congeals. However, studies over the past fifty years have shown that the visible simplicity is undergirded by a system of remarkable complexity. (Halkier 1992) In all there are over a score of separate protein parts involved in the vertebrate clotting system. The concerted action of the components results in formation of a web-like structure at the site of the cut, which traps red blood cells and stops bleeding. Most of the components of the clotting cascade are involved not in the structure of the clot itself, but in the control of the timing and placement of the clot. After all, it would not do to have clots forming at inappropriate times and places. A clot that formed in the wrong place, such as in the heart or brain, could lead to a heart attack or stroke. Yet a clot that formed even in the right place, but too slowly, would do little good. The insoluble web-like fibers of the clot material itself are formed of a protein called fibrin. However, an insoluble web would gum up blood flow before a cut or scrape happens, so fibrin exists in the bloodstream initially as a soluble, inactive form called fibrinogen. When the closed circulatory system is breached, fibrinogen is activated by having a piece cut off from one end of two of the three proteins which comprise it. This exposes sticky sites on the protein, which allows them to aggregate. Because of the shape of the fibrin, the molecules aggregate into long fibers that form the meshwork of the clot. Eventually, when healing is completed, the clot is removed by an enzyme called plasmin. The enzyme which converts fibrinogen to fibrin is called thrombin. Yet the action of thrombin itself has to be carefully regulated. If it were not, then thrombin would quickly convert fibrinogen to fribrin, causing massive blood clots and rapid death. It turns out that thrombin exists in an inactive form called prothrombin, which has to be activated by another component called Stuart factor. But by the same reasoning the activity of Stuart factor has to be controlled too, and it is activated by yet another component. Ultimately the component that usually begins the cascade is tissue factor, which occurs on cells that normally do not come in contact with the circulatory system. However, when a cut occurs, blood is exposed to tissue factor, which initiates the clotting cascade. Thus in the clotting cascade, one component acts on another, which acts on the next, and so forth. I argued the cascade is irreducibly complex because, if a component is removed, the pathway is either immediately turned on or permanently turned off. It would not do, I wrote, to postulate that the pathway started from one end, fibrinogen, and added components, since fibrinogen itself does no good. Nor is it plausible to start even with something like fibrinogen and a nonspecific enzyme that might cleave it, since the clotting would not be regulated and would be much more likely to do harm than good.
So said I. But Russell Doolittle—an eminent protein biochemist, professor of biochemistry at the University of California-San Diego, member of the National Academy of Sciences, and lifelong student of the blood clotting system—disagreed. As part of a symposium discussing my book and Richard Dawkins’ Climbing Mount Improbable in Boston Review, which is published by the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Doolittle wrote an essay discussing the phenomenon of gene duplication, by which a cell may be provided with an extra copy of a functioning gene. He then conjectured that the components of the blood clotting pathway, many of which have structures similar to each other, arose by gene duplication and gradual divergence. This is the common view among Darwinists. Professor Doolittle went on to describe a then-recent experiment which, he thought, showed that the cascade is not irreducible after all. Professor Doolittle cited a paper by Bugge et al. (1996a), entitled “Loss of Fibrinogen Rescues Mice from the Pleiotropic Effects of Plasminogen Deficiency.” Of the paper he wrote: Recently the gene for plaminogen [sic] was knocked out of mice, and, predictably, those mice had thrombotic complications because fibrin clots could not be cleared away. Not long after that, the same workers knocked out the gene for fibrinogen in another line of mice. Again, predictably, these mice were ailing, although in this case hemorrhage was the problem. And what do you think happened when these two lines of mice were crossed? For all practical purposes, the mice lacking both genes were normal! Contrary to claims about irreducible complexity, the entire ensemble of proteins is not needed. Music and harmony can arise from a smaller orchestra. (Doolittle 1997) (Again, fibrinogen is the precursor of the clot material itself. Plasminogen is the precursor of plasmin, which removes clots once their purpose is accomplished.) So if one knocks out either one of those genes of the clotting pathway, trouble results; but, Doolittle asserted, if one knocks out both, then the system is apparently functional again. While that would be a very interesting result, it turns out to be incorrect. Doolittle misread the paper. The abstract of Bugge et al (1996 a) states that “Mice deficient in plasminogen and fibrinogen are phenotypically indistinguishable from fibrinogen-deficient mice.” In other words, the double-mutants have all the problems that the mice lacking just plasminogen have. Those problems include inability to clot, hemorrhage, and death of females during pregnancy. Plasminogen deficiency leads to a different suite of symptoms— thrombosis, ulcers, and high mortality. Mice missing both genes were “rescued” from the ill-effects of plasminogen deficiency only to suffer the problems associated with fibrinogen deficiency. [3] The reason for this is easy to see. Plasminogen is needed to remove clots which, left in place, interfere with normal functions. However, if the gene for fibrinogen is also knocked out, then clots can’t form in the first place, and their removal is not an issue. Yet if clots can’t form, then there is no functioning clotting system, and the mice suffer the predictable consequences. Clearly the double-knockout mice are not “normal.” They are not promising evolutionary intermediates. The same group which produced the mice missing plasminogen and fibrinogen have also produced mice individually missing other components of the clotting cascade—prothrombin and tissue factor. In each case the mice are severely compromised, which is exactly what one expects if the cascade is irreducibly complex. (Table 1)

Table 1. Effects of knocking out genes for blood clotting components.

missing protein

symptoms

reference

plasminogen

thrombosis, high mortality

Bugge et al. 1995

fibrinogen

hemorrhage, death in pregnancy

Suh et al. 1995

plasminogen / fibrinogen

hemorrhage, death in pregnancy

Bugge et al. 1996a

prothrombin

hemorrhage, death in pregnancy

Sun et al. 1998

tissue factor

hemorrhage, death in pregnanc

Bugge et al. 1996b

What lessons can we draw from this incident? The point is certainly not that Russell Doolittle misread a paper, which anyone might do. (Scientists as a rule are not known for their ability to write clearly, and Bugge et al (1996a) was no exception.) Rather, the main lesson is that irreducible complexity seems to be a much more severe problem than Darwinists recognize, since the experiment Doolittle himself chose to demonstrate that “music and harmony can arise from a smaller orchestra” showed exactly the opposite. A second lesson is that gene duplication is not the panacea it is often made out to be. Professor Doolittle knows as much about the structures of the clotting proteins and their genes as anyone on earth, and is convinced that many of them arose by gene duplication and exon shuffling. Yet that knowledge did not prevent him from proposing utterly nonviable mutants as possible examples of evolutionary intermediates. A third lesson is that, as I had claimed in Darwin’s Black Box, there are no papers in the scientific literature detailing how the clotting pathway could have arisen by Darwinian means. If there were, Doolittle would simply have cited them. Another significant lesson we can draw is that, while the majority of academic biologists and philosophers place their confidence in Darwinism, that confidence rests on no firmer grounds than Professor Doolittle’s. As an illustration, consider the words of the philosopher Michael Ruse: For example, Behe is a real scientist, but this case for the impossibility of a small-step natural origin of biological complexity has been trampled upon contemptuously by the scientists working in the field. They think his grasp of the pertinent science is weak and his knowledge of the literature curiously (although conveniently) outdated. For example, far from the evolution of clotting being a mystery, the past three decades of work by Russell Doolittle and others has thrown significant light on the ways in which clotting came into being. More than this, it can be shown that the clotting mechanism does not have to be a one-step phenomenon with everything already in place and functioning. One step in the cascade involves fibrinogen, required for clotting, and another, plaminogen [sic], required for clearing clots away. (Ruse 1998) And Ruse went on to quote Doolittle’s passage from Boston Review that I quoted earlier. Now, Ruse is a prominent Darwinist and has written many books on various aspects of Darwiniana. Yet, as his approving quotation of Doolittle’s mistaken reasoning shows (complete with copying of Doolittle’s typo-misspelling of “plaminogen”), Ruse has no independent knowledge of how natural selection could have put together complex biochemical systems. As far as the scientific dispute is concerned, Ruse has nothing to add. Another such example is seen in a recent essay in The Scientist entitled “Not-So-Intelligent Design”, by Neil S. Greenspan, a professor of pathology at Case Western Reserve University, who wrote (Greenspan 2002) “The Design advocates also ignore the accumulating examples of the reducibility of biological systems. As Russell Doolittle has noted in commenting on the writings of one ID advocate…” and Greenspan goes on to approvingly cite Doolittle’s argument in Boston Review. He concludes with unwitting irony that “These results cast doubt on the claim by proponents of ID that they know which systems exhibit irreducible complexity and which do not.” But since the results of Bugge et al (1996a) are precisely the opposite of what Greenspan supposed, the shoe is now on the other foot. This incident casts grave doubt on the claim by Darwinists, both biologists and philosophers, that they know that complex cellular systems are explainable in Darwinian terms. It demonstrates that Darwinists either cannot or will not recognize difficulties for their theory.

The Mousetrap

The second counterargument to irreducibility I will discuss here does not concern a biological example, but a conceptual one. In Darwin’s Black Box I pointed to a common mechanical mousetrap as an example of irreducible complexity. Almost immediately after publication, some Darwinists began proposing ways that the mousetrap could be built step by step. One proposal which has gotten wide attention, and has been endorsed by some prominent scientists, was put forward by John McDonald, a professor of biology at the University of Delaware and can be seen on his website. [4] His series of traps are shown in Figure 3. McDonald’s main point was that the trap I pictured in my book consisted of five parts, yet he could build a trap with fewer parts. I agree. In fact, I said exactly the same thing in my book. I wrote We need to distinguish between a physical precursor and a conceptual precursor. The trap described above is not the only system that can immobilize a mouse. On other occasions my family has used a glue trap. In theory at least, one can use a box propped open with a stick that could be tripped. Or one can simply shoot the mouse with a BB gun. However, these are not physical precursors to the standard mousetrap since they cannot be transformed, step-by-Darwinian-step, into a trap with a base, hammer, spring, catch, and holding bar. (Behe 1996, 43)

Figure 3. A series of mousetraps with an increasing number of parts, as proposed by John McDonald (http://udel.edu/~mcdonald/oldmousetrap.html) and reproduced here with his permission. Yet intelligence is still required to construct one trap from another, as described in the text.

Thus the point is not that mousetraps can be built in different ways, with different numbers of pieces. (My children have a game at home called Mousetrap which has many, many pieces and looks altogether different from the common mechanical one.) Of course they can. The only question is whether a particular trap can be built by “numerous, successive, slight modifications” to a simple starting point—without the intervention of intelligence—as Darwin insisted his theory required. The McDonald traps cannot. Shown at the top of Figure 3 are his one-piece trap and his two-piece trap. The structure of the second trap, however, is not a single, small, random step away from the first. First notice that the one-piece trap is not a simple spring—it is shaped in a very special way. In fact, the shape was deliberately chosen by an intelligent agent, John McDonald, to be able to act as a trap. Well, one has to start somewhere. But if the mousetrap series is to have any relevance at all to Darwinian evolution, then intelligence can’t be involved at any further point. Yet intelligence saturates the whole series. Consider what would be necessary to convert the one-piece trap to the “twopiece” trap. One can’t just place the first trap on a simple piece of wood and have it work as the second trap does. Rather, as shown in Figure 3, the two protruding ends of the spring both first have to be reoriented. What’s more, two staples (barely visible in Figure 3) are added to hold the spring on to the platform so it can be under tension in the two-piece trap. So we have gone not from a one- to a two-piece trap, but from a oneto a four-piece trap. Notice also that the placement of the staples in relation to the edge of the platform is critical. If the staples were moved a quarter inch from where they are, the trap wouldn’t work. Finally, consider that, to have a serious analogy to the robotic processes of the cell, we can’t have an intelligent human setting the mousetrap—the first trap would have to be set by some unconscious charging mechanism. So, when the pieces are rearranged, the charging mechanism too would have to change for the second trap. It’s easy for us intelligent agents to overlook our role in directing the construction of a system, but nature cannot overlook any step at all, so the McDonald mousetrap series completely fails as an analogy to Darwinian evolution. In fact, the second trap is best viewed not as some Darwinian descendant of the first, but as a completely different trap, designed by an intelligent agent, perhaps using a refashioned part or two from the first trap. Each of the subsequent steps of the series suffers from analogous problems, which I have discussed elsewhere. [5] In his endorsement of the McDonald mousetrap series, Kenneth Miller wrote: “If simpler versions of this mechanical device [the mousetrap] can be shown to work, then simpler versions of biochemical machines could work as well … and this means that complex biochemical machines could indeed have had functional precursors.” [6] But that is exactly what it doesn’t show—if by “precursor” Miller means “Darwinian precursor.” On the contrary, McDonald’s mousetrap series shows that even if one does find a simpler system to perform some function, that gives us no reason to think a more complex system performing the same function could be produced by a Darwinian process starting with the simpler system. Rather, the difficulty in doing so for a simple mousetrap gives us compelling reason to think it cannot be done for complex molecular machines.

Future Prospects of the Intelligent Design Hypothesis

The misconceived arguments by Darwinists that I have recounted here strongly encourage me that the hypothesis of intelligent design is on the right track. After all, if wellinformed opponents of an idea attack it by citing data that, when considered objectively, actually show its force, then one is entitled to be confident that the idea is worth investigating. Yet it is not primarily the inadequacy of Darwinist responses that bodes well for the design hypothesis. Rather, the strength of design derives mainly from the work-a-day progress of science. To appreciate this fact, it is important to realize that the idea of intelligent design arose not from the work of any individual, but from the collective work of biology, particularly in the last fifty years. Fifty years ago the cell seemed much simpler, and in our innocence it was easier then to think that Darwinian processes might have accounted for it. But as biology progressed and the imagined simplicity vanished, the idea of design became more and more compelling. That trend is continuing inexorably. The cell is not getting any simpler; it is getting much more complex. I will conclude this chapter by citing just one example, from the relatively new area of proteomics. With the successful sequencing of the entire genomes of dozens of microorganisms and one vertebrate (us), the impetus has turned toward analyzing the cellular interactions of the proteins that the genomes code for, taken as a whole. Remarkable progress has already been made. Early in 2002 an exhaustive study was reported of the proteins comprising the yeast proteome. Among other questions, the investigators asked what proportion of yeast proteins worked as groups. They discovered that nearly fifty percent of proteins work as complexes of a half dozen or more, and many as complexes of ten or more. (Gavin et al. 2002) This is not at all what Darwinists expected. As Bruce Alberts wrote earlier in the article “The Cell as a Collection of Protein Machines”: We have always underestimated cells. Undoubtedly we still do today. But at least we are no longer as naive as we were when I was a graduate student in the 1960s. Then most of us viewed cells as containing a giant set of second-order reactions…. But, as it turns out, we can walk and we can talk because the chemistry that makes life possible is much more elaborate and sophisticated than anything we students had ever considered. Proteins make up most of the dry mass of a cell. But instead of a cell dominated by randomly colliding individual protein molecules, we now know that nearly every major process in a cell is carried out by assemblies of 10 or more protein molecules. And, as it carries out its biological functions, each of these protein assemblies interacts with several other large complexes of proteins. Indeed, the entire cell can be viewed as a factory that contains an elaborate network of interlocking assembly lines, each of which is composed of a set of large protein machines. (Alberts 1998)

The important point here for a theory of intelligent design is that molecular machines are not confined to the few examples I discussed in Darwin’s Black Box. Rather, most proteins are found as components of complicated molecular machines. Thus design might extend to a large fraction of the features of the cell, and perhaps beyond that into higher levels of biology.

Progress in 20th century science has led us to the design hypothesis. I expect progress in the 21st century to confirm and extend it.

Nachdruck aus Debating Design: from Darwin to DNA. (eds. WA Dembski and M Ruse), pp 352-370. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

Prof. Dr. Michael J. Behe ist seit 1985 Professor für Biochemie an der Lehigh-Universität in Bethlehem, PA, USA. Er studierte ferner Chemie an der Drexel University in Philadelphia, wo er 1974 mit einem Bachelor of Science abschloss. 1978 promovierte er an der University of Pennsylvania in Biochemie mit einer Forschungsarbeit über Sichelzellenanämie. 1978-1982 arbeitete er an den National Institutes of Health über die Struktur der DNA. Von 1982-1985 war er Assistenzprofessor für Chemie am Queens College in New York City.
Er ist Autor zahlreicher Artikel und hat unter anderem das Bestseller-Buch „Darwin’s Black Bock“ geschrieben, welches auch in deutscher Sprache veröffentlicht ist.

Bibliography

Aizawa, S. I. Flagellar 1996. Assembly in Salmonella Typhimurium. Molecular Microbiology 19: 1-5.

Alberts, B. 1998. The cell as a collection of protein machines: preparing the next generation of molecular biologists. Cell92: 291-294.

Atkins, P.W. 1998. Review of Michael Behe’s Darwin’s Black Box. www.infidels.org/library/modern/peter_atkins/behe.html.

Behe, M.J. 1996. Darwin’s black box: the biochemical challenge to evolution. New York: The Free Press.
2001. Reply to my critics: A response to reviews of Darwin’s Black Box: the biochemical challenge to evolution. Biology and Philosophy 16: 685-709.

Bugge, T.H., Flick,M.J., Daugherty,C.C., & Degen,J.L. 1995. Plasminogen deficiency causes severe thrombosis but is compatible with development and reproduction. Genes and Development 9: 794-807.

Bugge,T.H., Kombrinck,K.W., Flick,M.J., Daugherty,C.C., Danton,M.J., & Degen,J.L. 1996a. Loss of fibrinogen rescues mice from the pleiotropic effects of plasminogen deficiency. Cell 87: 709-719.

Bugge,T.H., Xiao,Q., Kombrinck,K.W., Flick,M.J., Holmback,K., Danton,M.J., Colbert,M.C., Witte,D.P., Fujikawa,K., Davie,E.W., & Degen,J.L. 1996b. Fatal embryonic bleeding events in mice lacking tissue factor, the cell- associated initiator of blood coagulation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 93: 6258-6263.

Cavalier-Smith,T. 1997. The blind biochemist. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 12: 162-163.

Coyne,J.A. 1996. God in the details. Nature 383: 227-228.

Darwin,C. 1859. The origin of species. New York: Bantam Books.

Dawkins,R. 1986. The blind watchmaker. New York: Norton.

DeRosier,D.J. 1998. The turn of the screw: the bacterial flagellar motor. Cell 93: 17-20.

Doolittle, R. F. A delicate balance. Boston Review Feb/March 1997, pp. 28-29.

Dorit,R. 1997. Molecular evolution and scientific inquiry, misperceived. American Scientist 85: 474-475.

Dutcher,S.K. 1995. Flagellar assembly in two hundred and fifty easyto-follow steps. Trends in Genetics 11: 398-404.

Gavin,A.C., Bosche,M., Krause,R., Grandi,P., Marzioch,M., Bauer,A., Schultz,J., Rick,J.M., Michon,A.M., Cruciat,C.M., Remor,M., Hofert,C., Schelder,M., Brajenovic,M., Ruffner,H., Merino,A., Klein,K., Hudak,M., Dickson,D., Rudi,T., Gnau,V., Bauch,A., Bastuck,S., Huhse,B., Leutwein,C., Heurtier,M.A., Copley,R.R., Edelmann,A., Querfurth,E., Rybin,V., Drewes,G., Raida,M., Bouwmeester,T., Bork,P., Seraphin,B., Kuster,B., Neubauer,G., & Superti-Furga,G. 2002. Functional organization of the yeast proteome by systematic analysis of protein complexes. Nature 415: 141-147.

Greenspan,N.S. 2002. Not-So-Intelligent Design. The Scientist 16: 12. Halkier,T. 1992. Mechanisms in blood coagulation fibrinolysis and the complement system. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Harold,F.M. 2001. The Way of the Cell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Hueck, C. J. 1998. Type III Protein Secretion Systems in Bacterial Pathogens of Animals and Plants. Microbiology and Molecular Biology Reviews 62: 379-433.

Kauffman,S.A. 1995. At home in the universe :the search for laws of self-organization and complexity. New York: Oxford University Press.

Miller,K.R. 1999. Finding Darwin’s God: a scientist’s search for common ground between God and evolution. New York: Cliff Street Books.

Pomiankowski, A. The God of the tiny gaps. New Scientist Sept 14, 1996, pp. 44-45.

Ruse, M. Answering the creationists: Where they go wrong and what they’re afraid of. Free Inquiry March 22, 1998, p. 28.

Shapiro, J. In the details … what? National Review Sept 16, 1996, pp. 62-65.

Shapiro,L. 1995. The bacterial flagellum: from genetic network to complex architecture. Cell 80: 525-527.

Suh,T.T., Holmback,K., Jensen,N.J., Daugherty,C.C., Small,K., Simon,D.I., Potter,S., & Degen,J.L. 1995. Resolution of spontaneous bleeding events but failure of pregnancy in fibrinogen-deficient mice. Genes and Development 9: 2020-2033.

Sun,W.Y., Witte,D.P., Degen,J.L., Colbert,M.C., Burkart,M.C., Holmback,K., Xiao,Q., Bugge,T.H., & Degen,S.J. 1998. Prothrombin deficiency results in embryonic and neonatal lethality in mice. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 95: 7597-7602.

Yonekura,K., Maki,S., Morgan,D.G., DeRosier,D.J., Vonderviszt,F., Imada,K., & Namba,K. 2000. The bacterial flagellar cap as the rotary promoter of flagellin self- assembly. Science 290: 2148-2152.

Fußnoten

[1] For example, microbiologist James Shapiro of the University of Chicago declared in National Review that “There are no detailed Darwinian accounts for the evolution of any fundamental biochemical or cellular system, only a variety of wishful speculations.” (Shapiro 1996) In Nature University of Chicago evolutionary biologist Jerry Coyne stated, “There is no doubt that the pathways described by Behe are dauntingly complex, and their evolution will be hard to unravel. … [W]e may forever be unable to envisage the first proto-pathways.” (Coyne 1996) In a particularly scathing review in Trends in Ecology and Evolution Tom Cavalier-Smith, an evolutionary biologist at the University of British Columbia, nonetheless wrote, “For none of the cases mentioned by Behe is there yet a comprehensive and detailed explanation of the probable steps in the evolution of the observed complexity. The problems have indeed been sorely neglected — though Behe repeatedly exaggerates this neglect with such hyperboles as ‘an eerie and complete silence.’” (Cavalier-Smith 1997) Evolutionary biologist Andrew Pomiankowski agreed in New Scientist, “Pick up any biochemistry textbook, and you will find perhaps two or three references to evolution. Turn to one of these and you will be lucky to find anything better than ‘evolution selects the fittest molecules for their biological function.’” (Pomiankowski 1996) In American Scientist Yale molecular biologist Robert Dorit averred, “In a narrow sense, Behe is correct when he argues that we do not yet fully understand the evolution of the flagellar motor or the blood clotting cascade.” (Dorit 1997)

[2] A good example is found on the “World of Richard Dawkins” web site maintained by Dawkins fan John Catalano at www.world-of-dawkins.com/Catalano/box/published.htm. It is to this site that Oxford University physical chemist Peter Atkins was referring when he wrote in a review of Darwin’s Black Box for the Infidels web site, “Dr. Behe claims that science is largely silent on the details of molecular evolution, the emergence of complex biochemical pathways and processes that underlie the more traditional manifestations of evolution at the level of organisms. Tosh! There are hundreds, possibly thousands, of scientific papers that deal with this very subject. For an entry into this important and flourishing field, and an idea of the intense scientific effort that it represents (see the first link above) [sic].” (Atkins 1998)

[3] Bugge et al (1996a) were interested in the question of whether plasminogen had any other role in metabolism other than its role in clotting, as had been postulated. The fact that the direct effects of plasminogen deficiency were ameliorated by fibrinogen deficiency showed that plasminogen likely had no other role.

[4] http://udel.edu/~mcdonald/oldmousetrap.html. Professor McDonald has recently designed a new series of traps which can be seen at http://udel.edu/~mcdonald/mousetrap.html. I have examined them and have concluded that they involve his directing intelligence to the same degree.

[5] Behe, M.J. “A Mousetrap Defended: Response to Critics,” www.crsc.org

[6] http://biocrs.biomed.brown.edu/Darwin/DI/Mousetrap.html

Verwandte Dateien

Kontakt